This assignment is designed to help you re
This assignment is designed to help you review APA writing guidelines and to begin finding references for the Critical Thinking that is due in Topic 3. This week you are going to start preparing for the assignment you have due in Topic 3. This will allow the instructors to review your research and give feedback you will use to develop the Topic 3 .
In Topic 3 you will be given 2 topics to choose from: Right to Die or Video Games and Violent Behavior. Two articles for each topic will be given that support each side of the controversy and you are expected to use both articles. Using the Class Resources find similar, empirical articles to support your rationale for the Topic 3 assignment
Use the resources found to construct an APA title page and reference section that conform to guidelines found in the Publication Manual of the American Psychological Association. Reference sections should include at least two articles, one e-book, and one electronic source.
This assignment uses a scoring guide. Please review the scoring guide prior to beginning the assignment to become familiar with the expectations for successful completion.
Prepare this assignment according to the guidelines found in the APA Style Guide, located in the Student Success Center
Innovations in CLINICAL NEUROSCIENCE [ V O L U M E 1 3 , N U M B E R 1 1 – 1 2 , N O V E M B E R – D E C E M B E R 2 0 1 6 ]12
ABSTRACT Managing individuals with chronic
disorders of consciousness raises
ethical questions about the
appropriateness of maintaining life-
sustaining treatments and end-of-life
decisions for those who are unable to
make decisions for themselves. For
many years, the positions fostering
the “sanctity” of human life (i.e., life
is inviolable in any case) have led to
maintaining life-sustaining
treatments (including artificial
nutrition and hydration) in patients
with disorders of consciousness,
allowing them to live for as long as
possible. Seldom have positions that
foster “dignity” of human life (i.e.,
everyone has the right to a worthy
death) allowed for the interruption
of life-sustaining treatments in some
patients with disorders of
consciousness. Indeed, most ethical
analyses conclude that the decision
to interrupt life-sustaining therapies,
including artificial nutrition and
hydration, should be guided by
reliable information about how the
patient wants or wanted to be
treated and/or whether the patient
wants or wanted to live in such a
condition. This would be in keeping
with the principles of patient-
centered medicine, and would
conciliate the duty of respecting both
the dignity and sanctity of life and
the right to a worthy death. This
“right to die” has been recognized in
some countries, which have legalized
euthanasia and/or physician-assisted
suicide, but some groups fear that
legalizing end-of-life decisions for
some patients may result in the
inappropriate use of euthanasia, both
voluntary and nonvoluntary forms
(slippery slope argument) in other
patients.
This review describes the current
opinions and ethical issues
concerning end-of-life decisions in
patients with disorders of
consciousness, with a focus on the
impact misdiagnoses of disorders of
consciousness may have on end-of-
life decisions, the concept of
“dignity” and “sanctity” of human life
in view of end-of-life decisions, and
the risk of the slippery slope
argument when dealing with
euthanasia and end-of-life decisions.
We argue that the patient’s diagnosis,
prognosis, and wishes should be
by ROCCO SALVATORE CALABRÒ, MD, PhD; ANTONINO NARO, MD, PhD; ROSARIA DE LUCA, MS, PhD; MARGHERITA RUSSO, MD, PhD; LORY CACCAMO, PhD; ALFREDO MANULI, MS; ALESSIA BRAMANTI; and PLACIDO BRAMANTI, MD
Drs. Calabró, Naro, de Luca, Russo, Manuli, A. Bramanti, and P. Bramanti are from the IRCCS
Centro Neurolesi “Bonino-Pulejo” in Messina, Italy; and Dr. Caccamo is from the Department
of Psychology, University of Padua, Padua, Italy.
Innov Clin Neurosci. 2016;13(11–12):12–24
FUNDING: No funding was received for the
preparation of this article.
FINANCIAL DISCLOSURES: The authors have no
conflicts of interest relevant to the content of this article.
ADDRESS CORRESPONDENCE TO: Rocco Salvatore Calabrò, MD, PhD; E-mail: [email protected]
KEY WORDS: Artificial nutrition and hydration;
euthanasia; minimally conscious state; right to die; sanctity of life; vegetative state.
R E V I E W A N D C O M M E N T A R Y
The Right to Die in Chronic Disorders of Consciousness: Can We Avoid the Slippery Slope Argument?
Innovations in CLINICAL NEUROSCIENCE [ V O L U M E 1 3 , N U M B E R 1 1 – 1 2 , N O V E M B E R – D E C E M B E R 2 0 1 6 13
central to determining the most
appropriate therapeutic approach
and end-of-life decisions for that
individual. Each patient’s diagnosis,
prognosis, and wishes should also be
central to legislation that guarantees
the right to die and prevents the
slippery slope argument through the
establishment of evidence-based
criteria and protocol for managing
these patients with disorders of
consciousness.
INTRODUCTION
Consciousness is the condition of
normal wakefulness (opening and
closing eyes, preserved sleep-wake
cycle) and awareness (of the self and
environment) in which an individual
is fully responsive to thoughts and
perceptions, as suggested by his or
her behaviors and speech. 1,2
A
disorder of consciousness (DOC)
results when awareness and/or
wakefulness are compromised
because of severe brain damage. 3
In recent years, the advances in
diagnostic procedures and intensive
care have increased the number of
patients who survive severe brain
injury and enter a vegetative state
(VS) (also recently named
unresponsive wakefulness
syndrome) 4,5
or a minimally
conscious state (MCS). These
entities represent the two main
forms of chronic DOCs. 6–9
In
particular, patients suffering from VS
are unaware of the self and the
environment and cannot show
voluntary, purposeful behaviors
because of severe cortico-thalamo-
cortical connectivity breakdown 10,11
that globally impairs sensory-motor
processing and cognition. On the
other hand, patients with MCS show
fluctuant but reproducible signs of
awareness and have a limited
repertoire of purposeful behaviors.
The best management of patients
in VS and MCS requires a correct
diagnosis, an evidence-based
prognosis, and the full consideration
of the medical, ethical, and legal
elements concerning DOC. 12
In
particular, patients with DOC need
artificial nutrition and hydration
(ANH) and, often, intensive
treatments. These issues evoke a
thorny ethical problem concerning
the therapeutic decision-making of
such patients (including the
continuation of life-sustaining
therapies) in view of the
uncertainties about their state of
consciousness, prognosis, and
personal wishes, with particular
regard to the end-of-life decisions
(ELD). 13
In fact, it is worth
remembering that the
implementation of any life-sustaining
treatment, including ANH, should
not be automatic when considering
that every individual should make his
or her own decisions regarding any
kind of therapy, according to the
ethical principles of autonomy and
the right of self-determination and
freedom. If an individual is unable to
make a decision, as in the case of
patients with DOC, a surrogate
should be empowered to ensure the
patient’s best interest and personal
wishes concerning ELDs. Therefore,
the right to lose health, become ill,
refuse treatment, live the end of life
according to one’s personal view of
life, and die should be guaranteed,
which is in keeping with human
dignity and the duty to protect
physical and mental health. 14
The right to die is further
supported by the following
arguments. 14–19
1. The right to (a worthy) life
implies the right to (a worthy)
death.
2. There is no reason to have a
“dedicated” right to die, given that
dying is a very natural
phenomenon, as is life.
3. Death is a private matter, and
other people have no right to
interfere if there is no harm to
others or the community (a
libertarian argument.
4. It is possible to regulate
euthanasia by proper laws, and
thus avoid the slippery slope
argument (SSA).
3. Euthanasia may avoid illegal acts,
given that euthanasia may happen
anyway (a utilitarian or
consequentialist argument) and
save the extreme despair of
suicide or homicide.
6. Death is not necessarily a bad
thing, owing to the naturalness of
the phenomenon, regardless of
whether it is induced.
7. Euthanasia may satisfy the
criterion that moral rules must be
universalizable, but
universalizability is a necessary
but not a sufficient condition for a
rule to be morally good.
8. Medical resources can be better
managed, and though this is not a
primary reason for the right to
die, it is a useful consequence.
On the other hand, an opposite
view states that life is a unique and
incorruptible gift that, in keeping
with the concept of the sanctity of
human life, must always be
preserved. Hence, each individual
has the moral duty to attend to all
the treatment necessary to preserve
life, with the exception of those
burdensome and/or disproportionate
to the hoped for or expected result
(i.e., life preservation), and to avoid
behaviors that can deliberately
hasten or cause death. 13,19–24
A possible middle ground is
represented by the concept that the
sanctity and the dignity of life are
somehow coincident; consequently,
there is no reason why accepting
euthanasia makes some individuals
worth less than others. Since it is
possible to regulate euthanasia by
proper laws, there is no risk of the
following: 13,19–24
1. Starting an SSA that leads to
involuntary euthanasia, thus
killing people who are thought
undesirable
2. Less than optimal care for
terminally ill patients (for
economic reasons)
3. Giving too much power to medical
staff in limiting the access to
palliative and optimal care for the
dying, pain relief, saving lives,
using euthanasia as a cost-
effective way to treat the
terminally ill, and limiting the
research for new cures and
treatments for the terminally ill
Innovations in CLINICAL NEUROSCIENCE [ V O L U M E 1 3 , N U M B E R 1 1 – 1 2 , N O V E M B E R – D E C E M B E R 2 0 1 6 ]14
3. Exposing vulnerable people to
pressure to end their lives (duty
to die) by selfish families or by
medical staff to free up medical
resources or when patients are
abandoned by their families.
At first glance, the problem of
ELDs in patients with DOC may
seem easy to solve. The supporters
of the dignity of human life claim
that since patients with DOC are
unconscious and therefore cannot
fully benefit from their rights, ELDs
should assumed by a third party
(e.g., those with whom the patient is
familiar, medical staff, ethics
committees, or courts).25 These
parties would make the ELDs, taking
into account the best interests of the
patient, his or her wishes, the right
to freedom, and the respect of
human dignity. On the contrary,
those who advocate the sanctity of
life deny any possibility to hasten (by
interrupting life-sustaining
treatments) or cause death (by using
euthanasia and physician-assisted
suicide) (PAS), because they believe
that life preservation is a social and
ethical duty. Moreover, patients with
DOC are in a very frail and
vulnerable condition in which they
cannot express their thoughts on
these issues.13,19–24
Judgements in the Schiavo and
Englaro cases highlight this
controversy. In the Schiavo case,26
the argument was over whether Terri
Schiavo was in a persistent VS,
which had already lasted 15 years. It
began with her collapse in 1990, due
to cardiac arrest, and then her
husband’s initial court attempt to
have her feeding tubes removed in
1998. That was followed by court
battles between the husband and
Schiavo’s parents, who opposed the
removal the feeding tube. Her
feeding tube was removed several
times and then reinserted after more
court orders. It was removed for the
last time in March 2005 after the last
successful court petition by the
husband. Schiavo died 13 days later.
Likewise, Eluana Englaro27
entered a persistent VS in 1992
following a car accident, and
subsequently became the focus of a
court battle between supporters and
opponents of euthanasia. Shortly
after her accident, medical staff
began feeding Englaro with a feeding
tube, but her father “fought to have
her feeding tube removed, saying it
would be a dignified end to his
daughter’s life.” According to
reports, Englaro’s father said that
before the car accident, his daughter
visited a friend who was in a coma
and afterward told him, “If something
like that ever happened to me, you
have to do something. If I can’t be
what I am now, I’d prefer to be left to
die. I don’t want to be resuscitated
and left in a condition like that.” The
authorities refused father’s request,
but the decision was finally reversed
in 2009, after she had spent 17 years
in a persistent VS.
Of note, the United States
Supreme Court has stated that the
irreversibility of a DOC condition and
the clearly defined patient’s wish to
not live under such conditions should
both be clearly demonstrated in
order to withdraw the sustaining
therapies, including ANH.28,29 These
decisions are fully in keeping with
the right of freedom and self-
determination and with the
supporters of the right to life.
However, these are fiercely criticized
and hindered by the sanctity of life
supporters.13,19–24
Therefore, we consider whether it
is more ethical to respect human
dignity than to protect the sanctity
of human life at all costs. A correct
approach to this thorny ethical
dilemma requires taking into account
that there is a tangible uncertainty of
DOC diagnosis and prognosis,
consequently making it more difficult
to respect a patient’s rights properly
when making ELDs. Moreover, it is
still debated whether ANH should be
considered a fundamental (i.e.,
always due) or an aggressive therapy
(i.e., useless and bearer of further
suffering).22,24,30–34 Finally, the
motivation sustaining the right to live
with dignity and in respect of human
life sanctity must be analyzed
carefully, given that the access to the
right to die is a SSA. In fact, both the
withdrawal and the maintenance of
ANH may lead to a chain of related
events that may culminate in some
significant and potentially negative
effects on patients with DOC (e.g.,
death or unnecessary and prolonged
suffering). Liberalizing euthanasia
may lead to unnecessary application
in some cases. The strength of each
argument in favor or against ELDs
depends on whether one can
demonstrate a process that leads to a
significant effect. SSAs can be used
as a form of fear mongering in an
attempt to scare the audience, thus
ignoring the possibility of a middle
ground between the dignity and the
sanctity of human life. In this article,
we will review the key concepts of
the positions supporting the dignity
and the sanctity of human life in an
attempt to find a conciliating view to
solve the SSA.
DOC DIAGNOSES AND
PROGNOSES
When family members are faced
with an irreversible and hopeless
case of unconsciousness, leaving
their loved one in such a condition
may be unbearable for both the
patient and his or her family
members. The relatives of patients
with DOC live a paradoxical reality.
In fact, they live with a family
member who is both present
(inasmuch as he or she is awake)
and absent (unaware) and alive
(inasmuch as he can open and close
his or her eyes, breathe
independently, and make some
movements) and dead (given that he
or she cannot interact with the
family members or the
environment).35–37 These issues can
foster denial or misunderstanding in
the family members of their current
situation. For example, they may
deny that their loved one is in a VS
because they interpret spastic or
reflexive movements as signs of
improvement,6 thus imagining
chances of recovery that are not
supported by evidence-based
medicine. Given that the family
Innovations in CLINICAL NEUROSCIENCE [ V O L U M E 1 3 , N U M B E R 1 1 – 1 2 , N O V E M B E R – D E C E M B E R 2 0 1 6 15
members may witness important
responses by the patient that have
not been observed by the clinicians,
the medical staff should attempt to
observe the patient with the family
members and involve them in the
patient evaluation. Assisting family
members in better understanding the
patient’s behaviors and level of
awareness is important and may
strengthen the family members’
relationship with the medical staff.38
Hence, the correct communication
of a proper diagnosis and a reliable
prognosis is essential for the best
management of a patient with DOC.
In fact, inaccurate diagnoses and
prognoses and disclosure of false
diagnostic information to families
may have serious ethical, medical,
and legal consequences regarding
the medical management of the
patient, the well-being of patient’s
family members, and ELDs.39,40 In
fact, an incorrect diagnosis and
prognosis may result in a false
expectancy for recovery by the
family members, the unnecessary
and potentially harmful life-support
prolongation of the patient, financial
and emotional resources being
withheld or withdrawn, resource
misuse and misallocation, and an
inappropriate rehabilitation or long-
term care facility enrollment.13
Nonetheless, identifying residual
awareness in unconscious patients
(thus differentiating VS from MCS)
and establishing a correct prognosis
are extremely challenging, owing to
the inadequate sensitivity of the
clinical and paraclinical approaches
currently available for DOC diagnosis
and prognosis.41–47 Even though the
rate of consciousness recovery varies
from eight percent to 72 percent
(but decreases to 20–30% in patients
persisting in comas longer than 24
hours),47 a severe brain injury may
result persistent unconsciousness for
many years. There have been cases
of emergence from DOC, even after
many years.48 Generally, recovery
from a metabolic or toxic coma is far
more likely than from an anoxic one
where the traumatic brain injury
(TBI) occupies an intermediate
prognostic position. A post-anoxic
coma is a state of unconsciousness
caused by global anoxia of the brain,
most commonly due to cardiac
arrest. The outcome after a post-
anoxic coma lasting more than
several hours is generally, but not
invariably, poor.47
About 40 percent of patients with
VS may be clinically misdiagnosed in
that they may be conscious but are
unable to manifest any signs of
consciousness.49–51 Such a condition
has been recently labeled functional
locked-in syndrome (FLIS),
whereby, using neurophysiological
and functional neuroimaging
approaches, clinicians are able to
record residual brain network
connectivity that is sustaining a
covert awareness.52 A patient with
FLIS is clinically similar to one with
VS, with the exception that the
former is aware of the self and the
environment but is unable to
demonstrate awareness or
communicate.6–9 This may due to the
deterioration of sensory-motor
processes, which support motor
function, rather than the breakdown
of cerebral connectivity.6–12,53,60
The low rate of correct diagnoses
and prognoses may depend on the
variations in scale application,
awareness fluctuation, and subjective
interpretation of clinical findings.
The use of paraclinical tests to
detect residual and covert signs of
awareness may help in better
managing patients with DOC and
consequently supporting their right
to ELDs. Nevertheless, different
paraclinical tests would be necessary
to confirm awareness since single
tests may suffer from the same
methodological bias that clinical
approaches do.39,40,54
ELDs AND THE DIGNITY OF
HUMAN LIFE
The thought of interrupting life-
sustaining treatments, including
ANH, may arise in family members
and caregivers when their loved one
suffers from a long-lasting and
potentially irreversible DOC
condition.34 The idea of hastening
one’s own death may occur when
one’s quality of life is poor or
unbearable (e.g., in the case of
physical pain and/or mental anguish)
and life is considered without dignity
(e.g., feeling there is no chance of
recovery, finding nothing that makes
life worth living, and perceiving life
as a burden to others).55–58 One might
consider that respecting the dignity
of life means respecting the dignity
of death and thus avoiding
unbearable and/or unnecessary
suffering or living in what one might
considered a handicapped and
hopeless condition. As stated by
Marc Augé,59 “To die without dignity
is to die alone, abandoned, in an
inhospitable and anonymous place, in
a non-place. To die without dignity
means to die, suffering needlessly or
to die tied up to a technical gadget
that becomes the sovereign of my
last days. To die without dignity also
means to die in isolation, surrounded
by insensitive people, soulless
specialists, and bureaucrats who
carry out their professional tasks
mechanically.”
Many authors22,24,30–34,60–62 criticize
using the interruption of ANH as a
way to hasten death because ANH
suspension inevitably leads to a
Collepals.com Plagiarism Free Papers
Are you looking for custom essay writing service or even dissertation writing services? Just request for our write my paper service, and we'll match you with the best essay writer in your subject! With an exceptional team of professional academic experts in a wide range of subjects, we can guarantee you an unrivaled quality of custom-written papers.
Get ZERO PLAGIARISM, HUMAN WRITTEN ESSAYS
Why Hire Collepals.com writers to do your paper?
Quality- We are experienced and have access to ample research materials.
We write plagiarism Free Content
Confidential- We never share or sell your personal information to third parties.
Support-Chat with us today! We are always waiting to answer all your questions.
