Critically evaluate Anselms ontological argument in his Proslogion. Critically evaluate Humes sceptical argument in his Enquiry Critically evaluate Malebran
need 2000 words (8 pages)
Please read carefully about the pdf and the comments on the word doc. to finish draft 2.
Essay Questions and the Argument Advice
PHIL1110 Introduction to Philosophy, Takaharu Oda
Summer 2022
Select one question from the following:
1. Critically evaluate Anselm’s ontological argument in his Proslogion.
2. Critically evaluate Hume’s sceptical argument in his Enquiry.
3. Critically evaluate Malebranche’s occasionalist argument in his Search.
Draft 1 (15%): 1000 words with an argument in premiss-conclusion form, due Class 8 (Wed) Draft 2 (25%): 2000 words on the same question and argument, due Class 17 (Tue) Final Essay (35%): 3000 words on the same question and argument, due Class 25 (Fri)
References
Charlesworth, M.J., ed. and trans. 1979. St. Anselm’s Proslogion: with a reply on Behalf of the fool by Gaunilo and The Author’s Reply to Gaunilo. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Clarke, Desmond M., ed. 2008. Berkeley: Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lennon, Thomas, and Paul Olscamp, eds. and trans. 1997. Malebranche: The Search After Truth. Plus Elucidations of the Search after Truth, translated and edited by Thomas Lennon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Millikan, Peter, ed. 2007. Hume: An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Essay Structure: Intro, Body Paragraphs, and Concl.
1. Introduction: the first paragraph should be up to 10% of the word count, and articulate two components:
i. Your thesis statement by answering and paraphrasing the essay question in your words (‘In this essay, I will argue that…’);
ii. Announcing your essay structure of each section or step. (‘In section 1, Berkeley’s argument is reconstructed… In section 2, I will consider an opponent’s view…’).
2. Body paragraphs: you will posit a philosopher’s argument in premiss-conclusion form, an objection to a premiss of it, and your response to the objection.
3. Conclusion: the final paragraph can mirror the introduction by paraphrasing.
4. References: don’t forget bibliography!
1
Argument Advice (modified from Dr Kenny Pearce)
By ‘argument’ in philosophy, we mean an argument in premiss- conclusion form. Therefore, (1) gather a conclusion and a set of its premisses for a philosopher’s argument, (2) make the argument’s deduction valid (i.e. logically connected), and (3) judge whether the argument is sound (i.e. all the premisses and conclusion are true) or unsound (some premiss is false and so is the conclusion).
Every essay question for this course will ask you to critically evaluate an argument contained in one of the historical texts we are reading. An argument is just a collection of reasons (the premisses) for endorsing some particular claim (the conclusion). These reasons are always offered to some particular audience—that is, there is someone the author is trying to convince. When an essay question asks you to critically evaluate—analyse and explain—an argument, this means that you will need to defend your own position on whether the audience should be convinced. In order to do this, you will have to get clear on how the argument is supposed to work. In evaluating an argument, follow these three steps:
Step One: Identify the Conclusion and its Premisses
W hom is the author (philosopher) trying to convince? Of what is the author trying to convince them? Often (but not always) the conclusion of the argument will be identified with words such as ‘therefore’, ‘so’, or ‘hence’. Sometimes the author will
say explicitly who the audience is; other times you will need to gather this from the text and its context.
For the conclusion, you will reformulate explicit premisses, which are the premisses that are directly stated in the text. Sometimes (but not always) they may be identified with words like ‘since’ or ‘because’. They may come either before or after the conclusion.
Step Two: Make the Argument Valid
A n argument is valid if the premisses guarantee the conclusion. In other words, if the premisses are true then the conclusion must be true. The premisses and conclusion of a valid argument might be true and they might be false, but if the premisses are
true then so is the conclusion. Conversely, if the conclusion is false then at least one premiss is false.
When you take logic next year, you will learn formal, mathematical methods that will allow you to tell whether very complicated arguments are valid or not. For now, we’ll stick to very simple arguments that can be seen to be valid without these advanced techniques.
Here are a few tips to help figure out whether an argument is valid:
• If the conclusion contains a new concept that is not anywhere in the premisses, the argument is not valid.
• If you can make up a story where all the premisses are true and the conclusion is false, and you can tell your story without contradicting yourself, the argument is not valid.
• Arguments that apply a universal principle to a particular case are valid (but only if the principle is absolutely universal). For instance, this is a valid argument:
P1. Socrates is human. [particular case]
P2. All humans are mortal. [universal principle]
C. Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
• Arguments of the form ‘If A then B; A; therefore B’ are valid, so called ‘modus ponens [mode that affirms]’. For instance, this is a valid argument:
2
P1. If Socrates is human, then Socrates is mortal.
P2. Socrates is human.
C. Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
You want to reconstruct the argument from the text in a way that makes it short, simple, and obviously valid, like these examples. In order to do this, you will usually have to paraphrase what the philosopher has written. Sometimes, you may also need to add one or more implicit premisses. An implicit premiss is something the philosopher assumes, but doesn’t actually say, that is needed to make their argument valid. For instance, if someone said, “Socrates is human, so he’s mortal,” we would know that that person was assuming that all humans are mortal, even though this was not stated. When adding implicit premisses, you should clearly indicate that you are adding an implicit premiss and explain why you think the philosopher would accept that premiss.
Making the argument valid is the most difficult part, but is also very important. If an argument is valid, that means that anyone who accepts all the premisses must accept the conclusion or, in other words, anyone who wants to avoid the conclusion must reject at least one premiss. This is crucial in determining whether the argument is convincing. Those convinced call the argument sound, if all the premisses can be true.
Step Three: Is the Argument Sound and Convincing?
T he audience should be convinced by the soundness of the argument only if the argument is valid and they have good reason to accept all of the premisses (truths). This means that, in evaluating the argument, you should think about
which premiss might be most vulnerable to attack, and how the premisses might be attacked. If you think the argument is ultimately convincing, you will need to examine all of the premisses to be true and show that the audience must accept all of them. If you think the argument is not convincing, then you need to identify one premiss and show that the audience need not accept it. In other words, for the audience or opponent, the unaccepted premiss is judged to be false, and thus the argument is to be unsound. This should be the main thesis of your essay, and should appear in a thesis statement in your first paragraph, and again in a conclusion in your last paragraph.
In evaluating whether the argument is convincing, it is a good idea to consider one or more specific objections that an opponent might give. All the above essay questions expect a specific opponent and ask you to engage with that opponent’s objections. But even if your chosen essay question in future does not do this, it is always a good practice to consider some objections to your thesis.
References for Logic Training
How to formulate an argument? Have a look at, for example,
1. forall x (P.D. Magnus, Albany, 2005)
2. Wilfrid Hodges (2001) Logic: An Introduction to Elementary Logic (if you buy a book on logic, make sure that the author’s answers to logic exercises are included. Hodges’s book is great in this sense. See below the quotation from Hodges)
3. Jay Rosenberg (1996) The Practice of Philosophy: Handbook for Beginners (If you cannot access the book, do ask me. I will scan and distribute more chapters that you request)
4. Openproof Project (Stanford)
5. Logic Matters (Peter Smith, Cambridge)
3
Hodges (2001, 36):
An argument […] is what a person produces when he or she makes a statement and gives reasons for believing the statement. The statement itself is called the conclusion of the argument (though it can perfectly well come at the beginning); the stated reasons for believing the conclusion are called the premisses. A person who presents or accepts an argument is said to deduce or infer its conclusion from the premisses.
Rosenberg (1996, 19): Rule One (the point is so important that there is no Rule Two)
Any opinion for which one can give reasons is admissible in philosophy, but once a claim has been supported by an argument, subsequent criticism must then engage the argument.
11 Top Tips for Successful Essay-Writing by Dr Brian Carey (Number 7 will surprise you!)
1. Don’t be afraid of the first-person pronoun.
2. Express complex ideas in simple language.
3. Define technical terms.
4. Use ‘signposts’: remind the reader what you’ve done, and what you’re about to do.
5. Avoid history lessons and biographies.
6. Get straight to the point. A shorter essay with only relevant content is better than a longer essay with irrelevant content.
7. Your conclusion should be almost a mirror of your introduction.
8. Don’t bite off more than you can chew.
9. Always stick to the question that you are being asked. This is the number one reason why students lose marks in essays and exams.
10. When you get to the end of your essay, make sure you’ve done what you said you would in your introduction.
11. Seven words that will guarantee you extra marks in every assessment you write from this day forth: ‘In this essay, I will argue that…’
For example, in the introduction:
In this essay, I will argue that Deep Space 9 (DS9) is the best Star Trek series of all time. I will begin in Section 1 by identifying two key measures by which a TV series ought to be judged – (1) quality of writing (2) quality of cast. In section 2, I will argue that DS9 ranks above all other Star Trek series on each of these measures. In Section 3, I will consider and reject the objections that DS9’s storylines were predictable and repetitive, and that most of its cast members were scenery-chewing hacks. Section 4 concludes.
4
,
2
Please read the following feedback and make changes to do a Draft 2: 2000 words on the same question and argument
the argument should be validated clearly, and attack one of the premises from an objector’s perspective. You may incorporate my revision into your next draft. Minus 1: although bibliography is fine, many of the citations are inaccurate. Add the section (§) or page number in each of your in-text citations. Reconstructing Gaunilo’s objection to a premise of Anselm’s argument with textual evidence will be much expected in the next 2000-word draft! Good luck
ESSAY DRAFT 1
PHIL1110 Introduction to Philosophy
Jiaxuan Li
Takaharu Oda
2022/6/11
Anselm's ontological argument on Proslogion was a proceeding from the ideology of having God to the realism of God. St. Anslem came up with the ideology on his Pproslogion of 1077 to 1078. The proslogion was brought about under the argument on the existence of God. In this paper, we I will evaluate the ontological argument evident in Anselm's proslogion. Section 3 of Anselm's reply takes us through the proslogion and major arguments about the faith-seeking understanding. Then follows section 4 of Anselm's reply that encompasses the evidence of the existence of God's "supreme being." Later segments discuss perceptions from arguments and the evidence that Anselm gave to justify his proslogion. Comment by 作者: This intro is concise but can be clearer. Enumerate all the sections you meant in this intro. I can’t see the details of sections 1 and 2 here. Also clarify more your thesis statement in terms of the essay question.
First, in section 1, Anselm responds to the arguments with the claim that when something is not existing everywhere and at all moments, even if it does exist at some place. Occasionally, it may be assumed not to exist anywhere or at any time. Anything that did not exist yesterday but does exist today might be thought of as never existing, even as Anything that did not exist earlier can be thought of as never existing (Anselm & Gaunilo,1992, §1). And Anything that does not exist here but does somewhere else can be viewed as not existing anyplace in the same way it does not exist here.
Secondly, in section 3, Anselm uses the standard form of the fools' argument to answer their criticism. He claims that the fools think "X" does not exist (premise 1). The "X" that the fools talk about is either the greater being, or it is not (premise 2). In conclusion, if the fools are not talking about the supreme being, they have not denied his existence. Still, if they are talking of the supreme being, they are imagining a contradiction that is not realistic. Anselm, in his Pproslogion, argues that "Even a fool has an idea of a being greater than which no other being can be conceived to exist. Such a being, he argued, must exist, for the very idea of such a being implies its existence" (Anselm & Gaunilo,1992). He claims that everyone knows what this tremendous being should be like. He claims that even a "dumb" may comprehend the existence of a being greater than all other beings. Even people rejecting the existence of God use this definition to describe him. Therefore, there is evidence of an existing supreme being, "God." Comment by 作者: The argument is not validly formulated, though it’s a good try! If you meant a disjunctive syllogism, P1 must deny one of the disjunctive clauses in P2, whereby the conclusion is deduced. You might have meant as below: P1. The fool assumes that ‘X’ does not exist. P2. The ‘X’ exists as a being than which nothing greater can be thought. C1. Therefore, the ‘X’ exists and does not exist. [Reductio ad absurdum, from the contradiction anything follows] C2. This contradiction means that the fool’s assumption can be false. You can add more premises to this valid reductio argument, as long as you can make it valid. Also, put the argument into a set of bullet points as I showed.
Again, Anselm creates a comparison of our perception of God with realism. Visualization of the taste of ice cream in a hot season, for instance, stakes in contrast to the realistic feeling. Since God is branded as the ultimate being, God should probably be bigger than the thought. Anselm continues to argue that because the idea of God is in existence, he should be real, as where else can people obtain the perceptions of God if not from Himself? He emphasizes that a supreme being is in existence and superior to one that is not existing. As a result, an entity, in this situation, God, must exist in order to be flawless. He goes ahead to paint an imaginative picture of a candle. He claims that everybody creates a mental image of a candle when they hear the word "candle" (Anselm & Gaunilo,1992). Similarly, St. Anselm contends in "Proslogion" that everyone imagines a superior deity in the same manner, and it confirms the existence of God's supreme being. Comment by 作者: Citation.
Additionally, in section 4, Anselm sends a reply to Gaunilo. Anselm describes that Anything will be considered non-existent with the exemption of the supreme. He continues to explain that only all the things that have either a beginning or an end made up of parts do not exist all the time and everywhere. Therefore, the existence of God, the "supreme being," is true as he exists everywhere and all the time. He concludes by stating that such beings, regarding their nature, cannot fail to be in existence everywhere every time. Comment by 作者: However, what is Gaunilo’s objection to Anselm’s argument? Explain which premise of A’s argument does G attacks.
Anselm is also backed up by philosophers who supported the existence of a supreme being. In Anselm's "Fifth Meditation," Rene Descartes, the famed Renaissance philosopher, adopted several of St. Anselm's concepts. He thought it was paradoxical to imagine a faultless and stronger entity while claiming they did not exist. He likened it to attempting to imagine a triangle with no edges that add up to 180 °, which is impossible because a triangle's inner angles must sum up to 180 ° (Anselm & Gaunilo,1992). He claims that based on this analogy, because humans can think of an ultimate being, the concept of one existing, and hence God should exist. Comment by 作者: Confusing. Comment by 作者: Cite Descartes. Comment by 作者: Which premise of Anselm’s argument do you mean? Signpost it and engage the argument.
Anselm explains why believing in God is significantly more logical than believing whether God is not real by speaking to the intellect. Knowledge of? an ontological thesis for the existence of God requires a thoughtful of the Proslogion. Our hHuman's grasp of inherent virtue (since humanity knows what is right and what is wrong) is a sign of increased ethical beliefs, and hence God's kindness is a type of factual love. It indicates that by reflecting on what is really 'excellent,' human being can deduce information concerning God's personality and character, finally 'understanding God.' Since God's personality is associated with goodness, this knowledge makes it evident that God exists beyond doubt. Comment by 作者: Unclear. Comment by 作者: Clarify. Comment by 作者: Citation.
Based on the arguments and evidence that Anselm provided, it is possible to affirm that there is the existence of a supreme being who is present at all times and all places. Premises support it concluded from fools' perspective and the above discussed elements.
In conclusion, Anselm's arguments have faced criticism and support from different philosophers. He managed to respond to the different opposing arguments by explaining the contradictions to their arguments. It starts with section 2 response on the existence of supreme being. In section 3 he is faced with the critic on fools' perspective where he addressed the issue of contradictions and impossibilities they exert to their claims. Section 4 reply from Anselm to Gaunilo on the existence of supreme being is directed to the existence of a being that is present in every place at all the time. It affirmed that there is the existence of God. The paper ends with logical evidence that Anslem gave concerning the existence of God and thus drives us to believe that God is in existence and his powerful awareness. Comment by 作者: Clarify in 500 words more in the next draft! Bear in mind that Gaunilo’s criticism sticks to one falsifiable premise of Anselm’s argument. Comment by 作者: If you justify A’s argument, then state that it is ‘sound’ for all the true premises.
References
Anselm, S., & Gaunilo. (1992). St. Anselm’s Proslogion: With a Reply on Behalf of the Fool by Gaunilo and the Author’s Reply to Gaunilo (M. J. Charlesworth, Ed.). University of Notre Dame Press. (Original work published 1979)
In the Proslogion, St. Anselm presents a philosophical argument for the existence of God. His proof has played an important role in the history of philosophy. Included in this edition are Gaunilo’s “A Reply on Behalf of the Fool” and St.Anselm’s “The Author’s Reply to Gaunilio”. Comment by 作者: Very good to note the objection of Gaunilo. But you can put this info into the body text. In bibliography, only the references make sense.
Collepals.com Plagiarism Free Papers
Are you looking for custom essay writing service or even dissertation writing services? Just request for our write my paper service, and we'll match you with the best essay writer in your subject! With an exceptional team of professional academic experts in a wide range of subjects, we can guarantee you an unrivaled quality of custom-written papers.
Get ZERO PLAGIARISM, HUMAN WRITTEN ESSAYS
Why Hire Collepals.com writers to do your paper?
Quality- We are experienced and have access to ample research materials.
We write plagiarism Free Content
Confidential- We never share or sell your personal information to third parties.
Support-Chat with us today! We are always waiting to answer all your questions.